Добавил:
Опубликованный материал нарушает ваши авторские права? Сообщите нам.
Вуз: Предмет: Файл:

учебный год 2023 / Judicial law making

.pdf
Скачиваний:
2
Добавлен:
19.12.2022
Размер:
1.9 Mб
Скачать

Limits of Judicial Lawmaking and Prospective Overruling Author(s): Wolfgang Friedmann

Source: The Modern Law Review, Vol. 29, No. 6, (Nov., 1966), pp. 593-607 Published by: Blackwell Publishing on behalf of the Modern Law Review

Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/1093007

Accessed: 01/06/2008 08:43

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use.

Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=black.

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

JSTOR is a not-for-profit organization founded in 1995 to build trusted digital archives for scholarship. We enable the scholarly community to preserve their work and the materials they rely upon, and to build a common research platform that promotes the discovery and use of these resources. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.

http://www.jstor.org

 

THE

 

MODERN

LAW

REVIEW

Volume 29

November 1966

No. 6

LIMITS OF JUDICIAL

LAWMAKING

AND

PROSPECTIVE OVERRULING

 

THE Blackstonian doctrine of the " declaratory " function of the courts, holding that the duty of the court is not to " pronounce a new law but to maintain and expound the old one," 1 has long been little more than a ghost. From Holmes and Geny to Pound and

Cardozo, contemporary jurists have increasingly recognised and articulated the lawmaking functions of the courts. The radical transformations which, for example, contracts, torts or family law have undergone at the hands of the courts have made it increasingly difficult to maintain the time-honoured fiction of the declaratory role of the judge. It is not, perhaps, surprising that it should have been abandoned more wholeheartedly in the United States than in

England. The profound effects, in all walks of life, of the interpretations of the Constitution by the Supreme Court-a Constitution which has in theory remained almost unchanged and yet governed the legal life of the country for almost two centuries-have long created in the United States a picture of the judge and his function very different from that traditionally cherished in England.2 The celebrated dictum that " the Constitution is what the courts say it

is " 3 has, if anything, been reinforced by the momentous decisions rendered by the court during the last decade in such matters as school segregation, voting rights and the redrawing of election districts. In England it may be that sheer respect for tradition, or

1 Commentaries (1808) 15th ed., at p. 69.

2The need to adapt the received common law of England to the diversity and dynamism of American conditions also tended to depreciate legislation and elevate the formative functions of the courts. " This depreciation of the statute

book was promoted by the pre-eminence of case-made, judge-made law in the formative first half of the nineteenth century; and this was reinforced, first, by

the office-apprentice system of legal education, and then by the spread of the case method in the law schools." Hurst, The Growth of American Law (1950),

at p. 186.

s Charles Evans Hughes, later Chief Justice of the United States, in an address to the Elmira Chamber of Commerce, 1907 (Addresses of Charles Evans Hughes

1906-1916 (2d ed.), p. 185).

593

VOL. 29

21

made financial statements,

594

THE MODERN LAW REVIEW

VOL. 29

perhaps a lingering love for the role of fiction as a major agent in legal evolution, is responsible for the survival of an increasingly untenable doctrine,4 which was, moreover, never adopted by some of the greatest of British judges from Holt, Mansfield and Blackburn to Wright and Atkin.

The House of Lords itself has now buried the remnants of the

doctrine. In three recent judgments the House has, in quick succession, asserted its lawmaking function, not in areas of marginal interpretation but of basic impact. In Shaw's case, the House of Lords asserted its power to supplement and, by implication, to depart from the statutory regulation of criminal law, through the revival of a common law offence called " conspiracy to corrupt public morals." 5 In Hedley Byrne v. Heller 6 the House, not content with the dismissal of an action for damages because the defendant had excluded legal responsibility, asserted, in a series of elaborate per curiam statements, a new legal principle of great financial importance, i.e., the responsibility of those who negligently make statements on financial soundness expected to be used by third parties.7 And in Rookes v. Barnard 8 the House revived an all but forgotten tort of intimidation, and resurrected the tort of conspiracy for economic disputes which had been all but buried in CrofterHandwoven Harris Tweed Co. v. Veitch.9 By establishing

4 Among recent judicial pronouncements in favour of the doctrine are those of Lord Jowitt, at the Australian Law Convention of 1951: " Please do not get

yourself into the frame of mind of entrusting to the judges the working out of a whole new set of principles which does accord with the requirements of

modern conditions.

Leave that to the legislature, and leave us to

confine

ourselves to trying to

find out what the law is."

 

Or Lord Simonds:

" For to me heterodoxy, or, as some might say,

heresy,

is not the more attractive because it is dignified by the name of reform. Nor will I easily be led by an undiscerning zeal for some abstract kind of justice to ignore our first duty, which is to administer justice according to law, the law which is established for us by Act of Parliament or the binding authority of precedent. The law is developed by the application of old principles to new circumstances. Therein lies its genius. Its reform by the abrogation of these principles is the task not of the courts of law but of Parliament." Scruttons v. Midland Silicones [1962] A.C. 446 at pp. 467-468.

It is not without irony that Lord Jowitt's remark was made in criticism of the attempt by Denning L.J. (as he then was) to introduce the principle of liability for negligently in Candler v. Crane,

Christmas d Co [1951] 2 K.B. 164, a dissent that has now been adopted by the House of Lords in Hedley Byrne v. Heller [1964] A.C. 465, while Lord

Simonds' refusal to contemplate a role of the courts in the adjustment of civil

liabilities contrasts with the same learned lord's ringing assertion of the sweeping judicial power in the field of criminal law, made in Shaw v. D.P.P.

[1962] A.C. 220.

5This assertion has opened up one of the most stirring controversies of recent times on the function of the law in general, and of the courts in particular, as

 

guardians of public morality. See especially Hart, Law, Liberty and Morality

 

(1962);

Devlin, The Enforcement of Morals

(1965) Chap. 5; Hart,

Criminal

 

Law and the Enforcement of Morality (1965), p. 31 et seq.

 

6

[1964]

A.C. 465.

 

Creativity

7

for a full analysis see Stevens, " Hedley Byre v. Heller: Judicial

8

and Doctrinal Possibility " (1964) 27 M.L.R.

121.

 

[1964]

A.C. 465.

 

 

9

[1941]

A.C. 485.

 

 

Nov. 1966

LIMITS OF JUDICIAL LAWMAKING

595

legal responsibility for damages in the case of a typical union action instigated by a union organiser and two fellow employees designed to coerce the employer (BOAC) into certain behaviour, the House profoundly modified the legal and economic status of trade unions, and neutralised the basic provisions of the Trade Disputes Act of 1906.10 It would strain credulity to assert that such sweeping modifications of both common and statutory law are merely " declaratory " statements, or refinements of the existing law.1

It is therefore time to turn from the stale controversy over whether judges make law to the much more complex and contro- versial question of the limits of judicial lawmaking. The continuing

validity and importance of the basic separation of functions, in a modern legal system, between the legislative, administrative and judicial branches of government is no less important than the

admission that the

judicial branch does indeed play a vital part

in the evolution of

the law. By and large, legislatures must be

responsible for the formulation of general principles of conduct

which are of general, publicly promulgated and prospective appli- cability to a given community for an indeterminate number of situations; administrators must apply such general principles to more specific situations and often to specific groups within the

community-even though administrative orders and

regulations

often have certain legislative aspects; and the courts

must apply

the prescriptions of legislators, or the generalised principles deduced from a series of precedents, to individual disputes. Such a separa- tion of functions is not confined to the democratic doctrine of separa- tion of powers; it is part of the essential structure of any developed legal system.12 In a democratic society, the processes of administration, legislation and adjudication are more clearly distinct than in a totalitarian society, where legislative and administrative proce- dures tend to merge and the judges are expected to be the executants of the political ideology of the government. But even in such societies, the three functions remain generally separate.

10For a full analysis see Wedderbur, " Intimidation and the Right to Strike," (1964) 27 M.L.R. 257. The decision was, in turn, partly neutralised by the Trade Disputes Act 1965, which provides, inter alia, that an action against a

trade union . . . in respect of any " tortious act alleged to have been com-

mitted

by

or

on

behalf of the

trade union shall not be

entertained in

any

court (s. 4 (1))."

It also exempts from liability acts threatening the breaking

of a

contract

of

employment, or inducing others to break such a contract.

See

Hickling

(1966)

29 M.L.R.

33, and Wedderburn, ibid. at p. 53.

 

11 See

now,

for

a

comprehensive

analysis, Stevens,

" The Role of a Final

Appeal

Court

in

a

Democracy: the

House

of

Lords

today "

(1965)

28

M.L.R.

509.

 

 

 

 

structural

requisites of a

 

 

12 For recent formulations of the

essential

developed

legal system,

see

Hart, The Concept of

Law

(1961), p. 95, and Lon Fuller's

requirements of generality, promulgation and prospective operation, which constitute the first three of his eight requirements of the " inner morality"

of law (Fuller, The Morality of Law (1964), p. 41 et seq.).

there is,

596

THE MODERN LAW REVIEW

VOL. 29

It is therefore a matter of both theoretical and practical impor- tance to inquire into the limits of judicial lawmaking. Only when we have admitted that judges do make law, does it become necessary and possible to distinguish the characteristic aspects of judicial

lawmaking from those of legislative lawmaking.

LEGISLATIVE INACTION AND JUDICIAL REFORM

The dilemma of the courts in deciding whether to reform the

law, in the face of legislative inaction, has recently been succinctly formulated by a distinguished American judge 13:

" It is now a commonplace that courts, not only of common law jurisdictions but also those which have codified statutory

law as their base, participate in the lawmaking process. The commonplace, for which the Holmeses and the Cardozos had

to blaze a trail in the judicial realm, assumes the rightness of

courts in making interstitial law, filling gaps in the statutory and decisional rules, and at a snail-like pace giving some forward movement to the developing law. Any law creation more drastic than this is often said and thought to be an invalid encroachment on the legislative branch....

It is the failure or inability of the legislature to act where nevertheless, a desperate need for creative law- making . . . Whether it be deadlock or a refusal to face up

to legislative or political hazards, there is often a deferral or refusal to act. Sometimes the reason is strongly based on the desire to permit the difficulties of the problem to be resolved

judicially by an evolutionary case-by-case approach in the decisional process, at least for a time, until the question is ripe

for legislative handling. Sometimes the reason is only the view that the common law solution is best because of nice

technical distinctions and because the need for harmony with other rules of law is deemed paramount.... These are some of the reasons which make for a strong lawmaking function in the courts, far beyond the interstitial and the gap-filling. These reasons, however, do not mean that it is all to the good and that courts are best equipped to perform the function. On the contrary, there are grave limiting factors: the limitations

of judicial procedure, political dependence upon other branches of government, and the isolated nature of the judicial office."

It is a difficult question for a court to decide whether, in the face of continued legislative inaction, it should intervene to change a manifestly unjust and outdated legal principle, sometimes at the

risk of stinging the legislator into retaliatory action, or remain

passive. Certainly the answer cannot be given in terms of subjectmatter. The long overdue reform of the principles of liability of

occupiers to visitors could easily have been carried out by the courts, by interpretations far less sweeping than those the House of Lords

13Charles D. Breitel, in "The Lawmakers," The Twenty-Second Annual Benjamin N. Cardozo Lecture (1965), at pp. 32, 38-39.

Today and Tomorrow (1959), pp. 46-47.

Nov. 1966

LIMITS OF JUDICIAL LAWMAKING

597

used in cases like Bonsor v. Musicians' Union 4 or Rookes v. Barnard.15 In the end the law was changed by legislative reform."

Such questions as the joint liability of tortfeasors, the immunity of public authorities (in the United States) from liability for negli- gence, or the rights of a married woman to occupancy of a matrimonial home could be and have been the subject of judicial as well as legislative reforms. In 1959 the Supreme Court of Illinois decided that it was time to do away with the absurd rule of immunity of local authorities from liability for negligence, in a typical case where a bus driver employed by a local school authority had negligently injured children riding to school in the bus.1' But although the court applied its new doctrine only prospectively,18 the Illinois legislature was stirred into action and restored the old doctrine. The Supreme Court of California, which, in 1961, went

even further by overruling the old immunity doctrine retroactively,l9 was somewhat luckier, in provoking a comprehensive study of the problem and an eventual legislative reform in 1968. There are those who would solve the dilemma by generally prescribing judicial inaction in the face of legislative inaction. This view was propounded by Professor Henry M. Hart in a symposium on " Courts and Lawmaking " held in 1958 at the Columbia Law School 20:

" The Constitution of the United States and each of the

state constitutions prescribe the ways in which bills shall become law. Failing to enact a bill is not one of these ways, even when a bill has been introduced and voted down. A

fortiori, the failure to act is not an authorized way of making law when no bill on the subject was ever introduced in the

first place. ... A legislature is a deliberative body. It is an instrument for arriving at a consensus, not an instrument for

recording a consensus previously arrived at, as if by some mysterious emanation from the electorate. To arrive at a consensus, the legislature follows an elaborate procedure of

investigation and consideration eventuating in the approval of a particular form of words as law. For the courts to treat the legislature as making law by any other means is to treat this procedure and this agreement upon a particular form of words as mere froufrou-without any real function."

But two such eminent and experienced judges as Chief Justice Traynor of the Supreme Court of California and Justice Breitel of

14 [1956] A.C. 104.

15 [1964] A.C. 465.

16Occupiers' Liability Act 1957.

17Molitor v. Kaneland Community Unit District No. 302, 18 Ill. 2d 11, 163 N.E. 2d 89 (1959). It should be noted that in the United States, the discredited doctrine of the sovereign's immunity from tort liability has, in

application of the ancient decision of Russell v. Men of Devon (1788) 2 T.R. 667, been carried to much greater lengths than in England, where statutory

public authorities, including school boards, have long been held subject to suit in tort.

18 On the meaning of the principle of " prospective overruling," see below, p. 602. 19 Muskopf v. Corning Hospital District, 55 Cal. 2d 211, 359 P. 2d 457 (1961). 20 Paulsen (ed.), Legal Institutions

tive at a certain date.

598

THE MODERN LAW REVIEW

VOL. 29

the Appellate Division of the Supreme Court of New York are far less categorical:

" Legislative inaction, total or partial, in a troubled area, may indicate a rejection of proposals; or it may indicate a warrant to the courts to exercise the traditional common law

responsibility of piercing out,

case by case,

the necessary legal

innovations. Unfortunately

there is no

rule

of thumb to

distinguish these contradictory indications;

the

only course is

examination of legislative purpose by investigation of sur- rounding circumstances and the available legislative history." 21

" However timely an overruling seems, a judge may still be deterred from undertaking it if there are cogent reasons for leaving the task to the legislature. There are no ready lists of such reasons, and a judge has no absolute standards for testing his own. It is for him nevertheless to articulate the

uneasiness he may feel about judicial liquidation of a precedent, however ripe it appears for displacement in the time and circumstances of the case that has brought it into question." 22

CRITERIA FOR LIMITS OF JUDICIAL REFORM

While the general proposition that, in the face of legislative inaction, the courts should also remain passive has proved unacceptable to courts of many countries, one observation in Professor Henry Hart's

critique deserves further attention: " To arrive at a consensus, the legislature follows an elaborate procedure of investigation and consideration eventuating in the approval of a particular form of words as law." The nature of the judicial function imposes certain limits upon judicial reform. A few years ago, the present writer sought to formulate the basic limitation of judicial reform as follows 23:

" Courts can and indeed are called upon to adjust rights and liabilities in accordance with changing canons of public policy. But because they develop the law on a case-by-case

basis they can not as can the legislature, undertake the estab- lishment of a new legal institution, ' an elaborate procedure of

investigation and consideration eventuating in the approval of a particular form of words as law.' "

The following were among the examples given by way of illustra- tion: the West German Constitution of 1949 abolished the statutory matrimonial property regime of the German Civil Code as incompatible with the new principle of equality of the sexes. In the expectation that a new statute would by then have been passed, the Constitution decreed that the old law should cease to be opera-

But for several years after that date the

21

Breitel,

op. cit., p.

12.

 

 

 

22

Traynor,

" La Rude Vita, La Dolce Giustizia;

or

Hard Cases

Can Make

23

Good Law," 29 U.Chi.L.Rev. 223, 233 (1962).

 

 

 

"Legal

Philosophy

and Judicial Lawmaking,"

61

Colum.L.Rev.

821, 839

 

(1961); reprinted in

Essays on Jurisprudence from the Columbia Law Review

(1963), pp. 101, 119.

and consideration

Nov. 1966

LIMITS OF JUDICIAL LAWMAKING

599

German legislature failed to provide a new matrimonial property law. Faced with this situation, the Supreme Court of the Federal

Republic 24 applied, as the nearest equivalent to equality, the regime of separation of property which under the German Civil Code was to apply where the statutory regime had been excluded and no other had been agreed upon. But the institutional reform, which involved a good many complex arrangements on powers, accounting or liquidation, could only be effected by the legislature. This was finally done by the new Matrimonial Property Act of 1957. Again, courts can interpret the word " children " in wills so as to reflect contemporary views which no longer penalise illegitimate children. But they cannot establish new institutions such as adop-

tion or legitimation. By contrast, it was suggested that courts were perfectly well equipped to abolish outdated distinctions such as those between " governmental " and " proprietary " functions, between " invitees " and " licensees," or between " administra-

tive " and " medical " acts as determining the liability or immunity

of a municipal authority, an occupier or a hospital.25 On the other hand, it was suggested that the substitution of comparative for contributory negligence, however desirable and justified, could not easily be introduced by the courts because " the effective carriers of liability are, in the great majority of cases, the insurance com- panies, and not the nominal parties. Judicial reform would therefore affect the whole insurance rate structure." 26

The view that the kind of law-reforming task which courts cannot properly undertake is that which requires basic institutional adjust- ments is supported not only by Professor Henry Hart's formulation

of " an elaborate procedure of investigation

eventuating in the approval of a particular form of words as law,27 but also by Chief Justice Traynor, who, like Justice Breitel, is convinced of the need for major and continuous participation of courts in the lawmaking and law-reforming process, but agrees with

the present writer " that the legislature is pre-eminently qualified to cope with such problems as contributory negligence. There are many such problems whose resolution entails extensive study or detailed regulation or substantial administration that a court cannot appropriately or effectively undertake." 28

Yet, the distinction between institutional change and the adjust- ment of liabilities, as a general criterion for what it is proper and improper for a court to do, is too simple. Not only are there border-

24 Civil Decisions (BGZ) Vol. 11, Append. p. 35 (1953).

25 See, for examplesof judicial reformin these fields, the decisionof the Court of Appealin Cassidyv. Ministerof Health [1951] 2 K.B. 343, and in Razzel v. Snowball [1954] 3 All E.R. 429; and the Americandecisions in Bing v.

Thunig, 2 N.Y. 2d 656, 163 N.Y.S. 2d 3 (1957), and Collopyv. NewarkEye and Ear Infirmary,27 N.J. 29, 141 A. 2d 276 (1958).

26Friedmann,op. cit., n. 23 at p. 841.

27See above, p. 597.

28Traynor, op. cit., n. 22 at p. 233.

600 THE MODERN LAW REVIEW VOL. 29

line cases, like Bendall v. McWhirter, where the Court of Appeal attempted to create a new quasi in rem status for the deserted wife, by constituting for her benefit an " equitable right " or at least an " irrevocable licence " to occupy a matrimonial home despite

absence of

title.29 There are also cases in which a.court

has-very

much like

a legislator-initiated a basic institutional change,

and

left it to

legislators and administrators to elaborate

the

basic

principles and work out the necessary institutional adjustments. This is more likely to occur in federal jurisdictions where a Supreme Court has the ultimate power of constitutional interpretation and thus a scope for lawmaking unrivalled in other types of legal

systems. The interpretation of " due process " or " equality " or " freedom of commerce " clauses means in effect a power of almost

unlimited sweep to lay down principles of legislation and administration, in accordance with changing ideas of public policy. Two famous recent decisions of the Supreme Court of the United States illustrate the magnitude of such lawmaking-and institution-

creating-power.

In Brown v. Board of Education 30-a decision that initiated

a period of almost unprecedented legal and social change in the United States-the Supreme Court held the racial school segregation system prevailing in most of the Southern states to be unconstitutional, thus overruling its own earlier doctrine that " separate but equal " educational facilities were compatible with the Constitution." 31 This decision set in motion a major reorganisation of school systems-far from completed-in which the Federal District Courts, enjoined by the Supreme Court to supervise and scrutinise the legislative and administrative changes, act as judicial executants of the Supreme Court decision. Although the court here did not " approve a particular form of words as law," it clearly set a new institutional pattern, leaving it to state legislatures and administrators to work out the details under the supervision of subordinate

courts.

In Baker v. Carr,32the Supreme Court went perhaps even further in the ordering of new institutional arrangements. Here the court considered a suit by a group of Tennesseans alleging that they had been deprived of their federal constitutional rights by legislation classifying voters with respect to representation in the General Assembly. The court held these allegations to be justiciable, and a denial of the equal protection guaranteed by the Fourteenth

Amendment.

This decision-which has been bitterly attacked as an

improper judicial interference in matters of political

decision-set

in motion a nationwide process of redrawing of both

federal and

29 [1952] 2 Q.B.

466, as revised in Westminster Bank v. Lee

[1956] Ch. 7.

The decision was overruled by the House of Lords in National Provincial Bank v. Ainsworth [1965] 2 All E.R. 472.

30347 U.S. 483 (1954).

31Plessy v. Ferguson, 163 U.S. 537 (1897).

82369 U.S. 186 (1962).

state election districts.

Nov. 1966

LIMITS OF JUDICIAL LAWMAKING

601

Again the court, in the course of deciding a specific complaint, laid down a new principle of the most far- reaching institutional implications, leaving it to legislatures and administrative authorities to work out the details.

Another example of far-reaching institutional innovation by a court decision is the revision of New York criminal procedure caused

by the Supreme Court decision in Jackson v. Denno.8" This held that the existing New York procedure was incompatible with the Supreme Court's ruling that "a defendant in criminal cases is deprived of due process of law if his conviction is founded, in whole or in part, upon an involuntary confession without regard for the truth or falsity of the confession." 34 As a result, the New York Court of Appeals held that, for future trials, New York State would adopt " the so-called Massachusetts procedure described in the Jackson v. Denno opinion at pages 878-879 United States Reports ' under which the jury passes on voluntariness only after the judge has fully and independently resolved the issue against the accused '

and has made express findings upon the disputed fact question of voluntariness." 85

In both these cases, the institutional and status change was initiated by the court, and it was left to the other two branches of

government-the legislative and the executive-to

elaborate the

change.

perhaps more generally acceptable to juris-

More frequent-and

prudential thinking-is

a give and take between courts and legis-

lators in the initiation

and elaboration of law

reforms. Thus,

in the early twenties, when the German mark slumped to unfathomable depths, the law courts took the initiative in refusing to uphold currency nominalism in the performance of contracts. They were confronted with the fantastic inequities produced by the ability of landowners, insurance companies, or pension funds to pay off heavy debts at virtually no cost, while the creditors found the work and savings of a lifetime reduced to nil. The courts used a general clause of the German Civil Code, which prescribes that all obligations are to be fulfilled " in good faith," to lay down certain rough

and ready principles of adjustment of obligations. But they were not in a position to prescribe a detailed scheme of revaluation, which entailed a great deal of actuarial, administrative and institutional

arrangements. This was later done by statute. Again, the series of Supreme Court decisions which reinterpreted the provisions of the U.S. Constitution with regard to civic equality, eventually resulted in certain institutional and procedural guarantees provided by the Civil Rights Act of 1965-which includes the appointment of Federal Registrars to supervise the fairness of registration of electors in the states.

83 378 U.S. 368 (1964).

34 At p. 376.

35 People v. Huntley [15 N.Y. 2d 72] (1965), p. 78.

Соседние файлы в папке учебный год 2023